CJ Visser
 LLB LLM PhD
 Senior Lecturer, School of Law, University of the Witwatersrand


 Volume 57 2024 pp 142 - 159
 Download Article in PDF


SUMMARY

This article examines the relationship between transformative constitutionalism, legal ideology, and the fault requirement in South Africa’s common law of personality. It emphasises the need to balance individualistic and collectivist values in alignment with transformative constitutionalism’s imperatives of personal development and social cohesion in the context of the law of personality. The ensuing analysis reveals that the current fault requirement, an exclusive reliance on intention-based liability, inadequately addresses the collectivist values crucial to transformative constitutionalism. This leads to an underappreciation of the complete constitutional social value of the human personality as a legally protected interest. The article advocates a solution within the transformative constitutionalism paradigm, proposing the horizontal application of fundamental rights and constitutional values. This approach facilitates the articulation of the comprehensive constitutional social value of the human personality, encompassing both individualistic and collectivist dimensions. In conclusion, the article calls for an adjustment of the framework of the common law of personality, recommending the introduction of negligence-based liability into the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum. This adjustment aims to enhance the protection of the human personality while effectively balancing individualistic and collectivist values in line with constitutional imperatives.

1 Introduction

Through the lens of transformative constitutionalism,1 this article re-evaluates the fault standard required for personality infringements (iniuriae) under the actio iniuriarum within the common law of personality.

Currently, liability for personality right infringements hinges on intention-based liability,2 excluding negligence-based liability.3 Scholars have scrutinised this standard extensively, with some advocating for a shift to include negligence-based liability due to historical, pragmatic, and constitutional reasons.4

Historically, intention-based liability under the actio iniuriarum represents a “penal relic” from the Twelve Tables era, a time when the distinction between criminal law and delict was blurred.5 Solely relying on this historical foundation is insufficient in a modern context.6 Contemporary delictual discourse has shifted focus towards providing plaintiffs with “reparations” for harm caused by defendants, necessitating greater flexibility in fault standards.7

From a pragmatic standpoint, establishing intent poses significant evidentiary challenges for plaintiffs.8 The subjective nature of intent ties the defendant’s liability to their specific idiosyncrasies, inferred from case facts, making it considerably more difficult compared to proving negligence, which relies on more ascertainable objective criteria.9

The direct horizontal application of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996, has entrenched personality interests protected by the actio iniuriarum as fundamental rights, enhancing their protection in positive law.10 Negligence-based liability is better suited to provide this enhanced protection by casting a wider net of liability than intention-based liability.11

Against this backdrop, this article presents additional constitutional and ideological reasons within the transformative constitutionalism paradigm for including negligence-based liability alongside intention-based liability. These reasons stem from the influence of legal ideologies and values on the fault framework within the common law of personality,12 implicating constitutional imperatives related to individual development and social cohesion.13

The realisation of these constitutional imperatives can be assessed through the horizontal application of fundamental rights and constitutional values to the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum.14 If these imperatives are not adequately realised, adjustments to the fault requirement are warranted.15 Therefore, this article examines how the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum is embedded in legal ideology and aligns with the principles of transformative constitutionalism.16

In the discussion that follows, the article first establishes the transformative constitutionalism paradigm in terms of legal ideology, values, and constitutional imperatives (Part 2). It then applies this paradigm to the fault requirement within the broader context of the common law of delict, addressing intention and negligence (Part 3). Finally, it evaluates whether the exclusive reliance on intention-based liability aligns with transformative constitutionalism principles, providing constitutional and ideological reasons for incorporating negligence-based liability (Part 4).

This article maintains a high level of abstraction appropriate to the transformative constitutionalism paradigm. It focuses on the conceptual and ideological aspects of the proposed fault inquiry and does not delve into the practicalities of incorporating negligence-based liability for all personality rights.17 These practical considerations require further study and fall beyond the scope of this article.

2 Transformative constitutionalism, legal ideology, and values

As previously mentioned, the transformative constitutionalism paradigm posits that legal ideologies and their corresponding values significantly influence the frameworks of private common law.18 These ideologies underscore the roles of private individuals in realising transformative constitutional imperatives, particularly those related to personal development and the maintenance of social cohesion within the broader collective.19 Therefore, this part of the article interrogates the interrelationship between these constitutional imperatives, legal ideologies, and values, and their balancing within the frameworks of private common law.

To provide an outline of a theoretical framework for this article, it is essential to delineate the interrelationships between constitutional imperatives, constitutional ideologies and values, and private common law ideologies and values. Constitutional imperatives find their origin in relevant constitutional values and represent a more concrete expression of the constitutional ideologies underpinning these values.20 From this basis, the transformative constitutionalism paradigm seeks to align the private common law with the Constitution.21 This alignment involves adjusting private common law ideologies and values to better fit the constitutional imperatives of the transformative paradigm.22 This is primarily achieved through the application of fundamental rights and constitutional values, resulting in adjustments to the framework of private common law. 23

Moving to constitutional imperatives, the transformative constitutionalism paradigm envisions an ideological basis for developing the common law of personality, emphasising the need to align the positive common law with the transformative tenets of the Constitution.24 These transformative tenets find more concrete expression in the constitutional imperatives related to personal development and the maintenance of social cohesion. 25

The constitutional imperative related to personal development conceptualises the human personality as encompassing physical, mental, spiritual, and moral qualities that capture the uniqueness of the human image in positive law.26 These qualities enable individuals to express their unique identity in the pursuit of a meaningful and fulfilling life.27 This imperative emphasises personal autonomy and self-realisation as integral aspects of the human personality, underscoring the importance of individual growth and development within the framework of transformative constitutionalism. 28

Similarly, the constitutional imperative related to the maintenance of social cohesion emphasises the shared characteristics of the human image that bind individuals together through solidarity and interdependence.29 This imperative underscores that the pursuit of a meaningful life is a collective human aspiration, supported by reciprocal respect and mutual recognition.30 These principles of reciprocal respect and mutual recognition serve as benchmarks guiding social interactions, ensuring the stability and cohesion of societal structures, which are essential for maintaining the social constitution of the broader collective.31

Transformative constitutionalism requires a nuanced understanding of human personality in the positive common law that integrates the aforementioned imperatives.32 On a further technical reading of these imperatives, the constitutional imperative related to personal development is more aligned with individualistic values while the imperative related to the maintenance of the social cohesion is more aligned to collectivist values.33 In turn, these imperative must inform and adjust the broader ideological continuum with South African private common law, which ranges from (classical) liberalism to (post-liberal) altruism.34

Classical liberalism frames individuals as “atomistic units” whose personal autonomy competes with that of others.35 Accordingly, individuals are tasked with respecting each other’s personal autonomy by refraining from deliberate infringements36 This ideology emphasises individualistic values such as self-interest, self-reliance, and self-determination. 37

Conversely, (post-liberal) altruism views individuals as “interconnected selves” whose personal autonomy is constituted not only through individual abilities and achievements but also through social relationships and community membership.38 This perspective imposes a duty on individuals to exercise reasonable care to avoid carelessly infringing on the interests of others.39 This ideology highlights collectivist values such as cooperation, solidarity, and interdependence.40

Within the transformative constitutionalism paradigm, an appropriate balance must be achieved between individualistic and collectivist values within the frameworks of private common law for several reasons.41

First, South African private common law was historically constituted within a pre-constitutional ideology of (classical) liberalism.42 Classical liberalism tends to entrench the status quo of a pre-constitutional South African legal society43 and is therefore unable to adequately realise constitutional transformative imperatives related to personal development and social cohesion in a more egalitarian and socially just legal society.44 Accordingly, a constitutional ideological shift is required within the frameworks of private common law.45 This shift involves moving from pre-constitutional notions of (classical) liberalism towards greater (post-liberal) altruism.46 However, certain caveats are attached to this ideological shift: individuals cannot remain completely unfettered nor be entirely subsumed into the collective.47 This implies that the transformative constitutionalism paradigm does not advocate for a blanket rejection of individualistic values or a wholesale acceptance of collectivist values.48 Instead, it calls for a balanced integration where no set of values is privileged at the expense of another.49

Secondly, an appropriate balance between individualistic and collectivist values within the frameworks of private common law is essential to ensure that individual interests are sufficiently recognised and linked with the interests of the community.50 Failure to strike this balance could lead to either insufficient or excessive protection of individual interests in relation to their constitutional social value.51 Insufficient protection may hinder personal development by failing to adequately recognise individual abilities and achievements.52 Conversely, excessive protection of individual interests could place an undue burden on society and undermine social stability.53

Lastly, achieving this balance is crucial for giving effect to the “single-system-of-law” principle, a foundational pillar of transformative constitutionalism.54 This principle resists a stark divide between private common law and the Constitution by integrating public values into private law, facilitating the horizontal application of the Constitution.55 In concrete terms, this integration connects individual and collective interests to the Constitution’s objective normative value system, which consists of constitutional values and fundamental rights.56 Foundational values such as human dignity, equality, freedom, and ubuntu guide private relationships, providing interpretative norms for their constitutional regulation.57 These norms further assist in realising transformative constitutional imperatives by contextualising individuals within a constitutional community.58 Through the principle of adjudicative subsidiarity,59 individual interests and those of the broader collective are connected to corresponding fundamental rights, reinforcing the single-system-of-law principle and ensuring that private common law and the Constitution are not treated as distinct sources of law.60 In this way, these interests are also localised within the aforementioned transformative constitutional imperatives.

Building on this foundation, the next section interrogates the fault requirement within the common law of delict and the common law of personality, examining how these principles can be aligned with transformative constitutionalism.

3 Legal ideology, fault, and the common law of delict

When viewed ideologically, the common law of delict functions as a mechanism to regulate the allocation of losses for harm suffered by a plaintiff concerning their property, person, or personality, attributable to the defendant’s conduct.61 This allocation balances the plaintiff’s and

defendant’s individual interests against the broader societal interests.62 Specifically, the fault requirement in delict law seeks to establish the defendant’s blameworthiness by determining the expected standard of care.63 This determination rests primarily on two forms of fault: intent and negligence, notwithstanding strict liability in certain exceptional circumstances.64 These forms of fault embody varying degrees of individualistic and collectivist values in imputing blameworthiness.65 This part of the article critically examines the interplay between these values through the lenses of intent and negligence in the common law of delict.

With intent (dolus), a defendant is held liable for causing harm “deliberately.”66 In positive law, this manifests when the defendant had a legally reprehensible state of mind, characterised by directing their will to cause harm with an accompanying consciousness of its wrongfulness.67 Thus, intent comprises both the direction of will and knowledge of wrongfulness. 68 Determining intent necessitates an inquiry into the subjective state of mind of the defendant to infer their deliberate intent to cause harm, cognisant of its wrongful nature.69

From an ideological perspective, intent reflects a duty not to deliberately harm others, aligning closely with classical liberalism. This standard of care underscores individualistic values such as self-interest, self-reliance, and self-determination. The threshold of blameworthiness is rooted in the subjective mind of the defendant, integrating their specific individual characteristics.70 Consequently, intent aligns strongly with individualistic values.

However, the sub-components of intent - direction of will and knowledge of wrongfulness - also resonate with societal expectations regarding deliberate harm. Every individual who deliberately causes harm is measured against these sub-components to address the impact of their conduct on the broader community.71

Thus, while intent primarily reflects individualistic values, it also incorporates a weaker reliance on collectivist values.72

On the other hand, with negligence (culpa), a defendant is blamed for causing harm “carelessly.”73 In positive law, negligence is established when a “reasonable person” would have acted differently under similar circumstances, making the harm foreseeable and preventable.74 Negligence employs the reasonable person standard to assess whether the defendant exercised the requisite care, considering the specific circumstances of the case while avoiding a high level of abstraction.75

Ideologically, negligence embodies a duty to exercise reasonable care to avoid causing harm to others, resonating with post-liberal altruism. This standard of care emphasises collectivist values such as cooperation, solidarity, and interdependence.76 The threshold of blameworthiness is based on societal expectations, encapsulated in the reasonable person standard.77 This approach focuses on what a hypothetical reasonable person would have done in similar circumstances, considering the context but not the defendant’s unique personal characteristics. 78

Therefore, negligence strongly aligns with collectivist values, emphasising the duty to prevent harm through reasonable care. While individual circumstances are relevant, they are not prioritised, resulting in a weaker reliance on individualistic values.79

When comparing intent with negligence, it becomes evident that these fault standards complement each other in balancing individualistic and collectivist values.80 Intent emphasises individualistic values by considering the defendant’s specific characteristics and confining liability to deliberate acts. This allows individuals’ greater freedom of action, as liability is limited to intentional harm.81 In this respect, intent casts the net of liability narrowly.82 In contrast, negligence emphasises collectivist values by holding defendants accountable to societal standards of care, extending liability to careless acts.83 In this respect, negligence casts the net of liability wider than intention, ensuring the maximum protection of the individual interests of a plaintiff.84 This ensures broader protection of the plaintiff’s interests by encompassing both deliberate and careless harm.

A hypothetical example illustrating these principles involves a journalist who publishes a personal story about an individual’s health condition without explicit consent. Suppose the journalist assumes consent based on previous informal discussions but fails to verify it formally. Here, the criteria for intent would not be met due to the lack of direction of will and consciousness of wrongfulness. The journalist did not deliberately intend to harm the individual, nor were they aware that publishing the story would be wrongful without consent. However, the journalist’s failure to verify consent meets the criteria of negligence, as a reasonable person would have confirmed consent before publication. The reasonable person standard requires the defendant to foresee the potential harm and take steps to prevent it. In this hypothetical, the journalist’s oversight reflects a failure to exercise reasonable care, highlighting the importance of verifying sensitive information. 85

In essence, the availability of these two forms of fault in the common law of delict seems to work in tandem to ensure that an appropriate balance is achieved between individualistic and collectivist values and that the necessary protection is afforded to individual and collective interests.86

Against this backdrop, the article raises pivotal questions about the adequacy of an exclusive reliance on intention-based liability for personality infringements under the actio iniuriarum. Can such an approach facilitate an appropriate balance between individualistic and collectivist values, as necessitated by transformative constitutionalism? Furthermore, does intent alone provide sufficient protection for personality interests within their constitutional social context? These questions probe deeper into whether the current fault standard under the actio iniuriarum aligns with the constitutional imperative of transformative justice. The subsequent part of this article addresses these critical inquiries, evaluating the potential integration of negligence-based liability to enhance the protection of personality rights.

4 Legal ideology, fault, and the common law of personality

Regarding the first question, it becomes clear from the discussions above that an exclusive focus on intention-based liability cannot effectively balance individualistic and collectivist values within the common law framework of personality. As demonstrated, intent is predominantly underpinned by individualistic values through its standard of care, firmly situated in the ideology of classical liberalism. Intention-based fault focuses on the defendant’s subjective state of mind, emphasising individual autonomy, self-interest, and personal responsibility. This approach aligns with classical liberal principles, where personal freedom and self-reliance are paramount. However, intent lacks internal mechanisms to counterbalance its strong reliance on individualistic values and the advancement of classical liberalism.

Conversely, negligence is closely associated with collectivist values and post-liberal altruism. Negligence-based fault considers the defendant’s failure to meet an objective standard of care, measured against societal expectations of a reasonable person. Negligence promotes values such as cooperation, solidarity, and the duty to prevent harm to others, reflecting a broader social perspective. However, similar to intent, negligence cannot internally counterbalance its reliance on collectivist values. Therefore, integrating both intention-based and negligence-based liability provides an external counterbalance, that is, the other form of fault, effectively balancing individualistic and collectivist values within the legal framework.

From a different perspective, exclusive reliance on intention-based liability cannot facilitate a constitutional ideological shift in the common law of personality from (classical) liberalism to (post-liberal) altruism, as required by transformative constitutionalism. Intent is deeply embedded in classical liberal ideology, where individualistic values dominate the roles of private individuals in realising constitutional imperatives. Intent does not possess significant internal mechanisms to facilitate a shift towards collectivism, given its weak reliance on collectivist values. Consequently, achieving a socially just and egalitarian society becomes elusive as the emphasis on individual autonomy diminishes human interdependence, solidarity, and cooperation.87 More specifically, with intent, individuals are tasked to “mind their own business” and are not required to share or sacrifice the pursuit of their individual interests.88 Arguably, this willingness to sacrifice or, at the very least, share the pursuit of individual interests, is a necessary condition to realise the constitutional imperative related to the broader collective.89

Therefore, this article argues that intention-based liability alone cannot balance individualistic and collectivist values as required by transformative constitutionalism. This assertion is not merely theoretical but also has pragmatic relevance in positive law. This relates to the second question of whether sufficient protection is afforded to the human personality in relation to its constitutional social value under transformative constitutionalism.

When framing the human personality in classical liberal (individualistic) terms through the fault requirement, its constitutional social value appears limited to individual development. The human personality is conceptualised as an “individualistic good” without collective relevance.90 Consequently, there is a perception that there is no constitutional impetus to provide extensive protection to this interest.91 This notion manifests in the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum, where liability for personality infringement is narrowly construed through intent rather than negligence. 92

However, this article argues that pre-constitutional notions of classical liberalism can be escaped by ideologically adjusting the common law of personality to fit the transformative constitutionalism paradigm.93 This assertion is based on the horizontal application of fundamental rights and foundational values to create a single constitutionalised common law of personality, balancing individualistic and collectivist values.94 In doing so, the constitutional social value of the human personality can be re-evaluated through the horizontal application of fundamental rights.95 The collective dimension of the human personality, currently unarticulated in the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum, can be highlighted through the horizontal application of foundational values.96

The development of these assertions culminates in the argument that the human personality has immense constitutional social value, requiring increased protection in the common law of personality.97 This necessitates adjusting the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum to include negligence-based liability alongside intention-based liability.

Starting with the horizontal application of fundamental rights, the principle of adjudicative subsidiarity under transformative constitutionalism links a plaintiff’s delictually protected interests in property, person, and personality to corresponding rights in the Bill of Rights.98 For instance, a plaintiff’s interest in property is protected by section 25 of the Constitution,99 their bodily interests by section 12,100 and their personality by section 10 (human dignity), section 14 (privacy), and section 12 (bodily integrity).101 With the human personality, sections 10, 14, and 12 collectively ensure that the plaintiff’s interests are constitutionally recognised and protected, providing a robust framework for safeguarding personality rights.

The entrenchment of these interests through fundamental rights has significant constitutional ideological implications. Constitutional jurisprudence affirms that rights in the Bill of Rights generally enjoy equal status, implying that a plaintiff’s interests in property, person, and personality should receive equal protection in positive law.102 Ideologically, this suggests that a plaintiff’s interests in personality should not be afforded inferior protection compared to their property or bodily interests.103 This assertion is further justified by the horizontal application of constitutional values.

The horizontal application of constitutional values provides interpretative norms highlighting the individual and collectivist dimensions of the human personality.104 This involves contextualising the human personality against values such as human dignity, equality, freedom, and ubuntu.105

Human dignity relates to an individual’s absolute worth, rooted in both unique human characteristics and our shared humanity.106 These unique characteristics include bodily integrity, freedom, reputation, dignity, privacy, identity, and feelings,107 all of which enable individuals to pursue a meaningful life within the constitutional imperative of self-development.108 This represents the individualistic dimension of the human personality. Meanwhile, our shared humanity creates a vision where individual development is contextualised within a community.109 Within this community, the development of individual personalities must be supported and respected by other individuals and the broader collective to maintain social cohesion.110 This collectivist dimension of human dignity lays the foundation for the broader collective to develop its own cultural identity and preserve the stability of social life.111 Thus, human dignity embodies both the individualistic and collectivist dimensions of the human personality, reflecting the constitutional imperatives of self-development and social cohesion.

Within the context of the common law of personality, the values of equality, freedom, and ubuntu form an affirmative and mutually supportive triad. These values further support individuals in reaching their full potential and maintaining social cohesion through their unique characteristics and shared humanity, by providing them with social citizenship in a broader community.112

Equality ensures each individual’s social citizenship, allowing meaningful participation in social life regardless of material conditions. It emphasises that all individuals are entitled to equal concern and respect, which directly impacts their ability to participate fully in society.113 This value promotes the idea that every person should have an equal opportunity to develop their personality and contribute to the community, regardless of their socio-economic status.114

Freedom ensures individuals can reach their potential and establish positive relationships without unjustifiable restraint.115 This value supports the notion that personal autonomy and freedom are essential for self-development and the pursuit of personal goals.116 However, freedom must be balanced with the rights and freedoms of others, ensuring that one’s actions do not harm the community’s social fabric.117

Ubuntu advances the social ideal that recognition and protection of individual interests are interdependent on similar recognition and protection for others.118 It embodies the principle that humanity is interconnected, and one’s well-being is intrinsically linked to the well-being of others.119 This value highlights the importance of mutual support, empathy, and collective responsibility in fostering a harmonious society. 120

Considering the horizontal application of these constitutional values, it is evident that personality interests extend beyond individual development to include social cohesion. The human personality’s collectivist dimension facilitates constitutional imperatives related to social cohesion, providing the basis for social citizenship. The social constitution of the broader collective depends on the harmonious exercise of social citizenship among individuals. Therefore, under transformative constitutionalism, the collectivist nature of the human personality must be recognised in positive law through the fault requirement.

Flowing from the discussion above, the plaintiff’s personality interests should receive the same protection as their property and bodily interests, as highlighted through the horizontal application of fundamental rights. The human personality is not only an individualistic good but also a collectivist good, as emphasised through the horizontal application of constitutional values. The human personality encompasses both individualistic aspects, such as bodily integrity, freedom, reputation, dignity, privacy, identity, and feelings, and collectivist aspects, rooted in shared humanity and the need for social cohesion. Both individuals and the greater collective have a vested interest in the development of personalities, as the exercise of social citizenship to participate in social life requires an appropriate balance between individualistic and collectivist values. Achieving this balance ensures the social cohesion and stability of the broader collective, thereby reflecting the constitutional imperatives of self-development and community well-being.

Given the human personality’s social constitutional value, comprising both individualistic and collectivist dimensions, intent alone does not provide adequate protection. The ideological dimensions of the transformative constitutionalism paradigm necessitate enhanced protection of the human personality in positive law. This enhancement can be achieved by introducing negligence-based liability alongside intention-based liability. Incorporating negligence-based liability addresses the constitutional ideological concerns by ensuring that the human personality receives comprehensive protection that reflects both individual and collective interests. This adjustment to the framework of the common law of personality will align it with the broader framework of the common law of delict, thereby ensuring legal certainty and predictability. Introducing negligence-based liability complements intention-based liability, providing a more robust and balanced approach to safeguarding personality rights within the transformative constitutionalism paradigm.

5 Conclusion

This article has examined the relationship between transformative constitutionalism, legal ideology, and the fault requirement in the common law of personality. It has emphasised the necessity of striking an adequate balance between individualistic and collectivist values, in alignment with the constitutional imperatives of individual development and social cohesion within the transformative constitutionalism paradigm.

The analysis reveals that the exclusive reliance on intention-based liability in the fault requirement inadequately addresses the collectivist values endorsed by post-liberal altruism, as demanded by transformative constitutionalism. Furthermore, it becomes evident that the full constitutional social value of the human personality, as a delictually protected interest, remains underappreciated and unarticulated within this framework. However, through the horizontal application of fundamental rights and constitutional values, as outlined in the transformative constitutionalism paradigm, the articulation of the comprehensive constitutional social value of the human personality is facilitated, encompassing both its individualistic and collectivist dimensions.

In light of these insights and considerations, it is imperative to adjust the framework of the common law of personality to introduce negligence-based liability in the fault requirement of the actio iniuriarum. This adjustment is essential to provide adequate protection to the human personality while effectively balancing individualistic and collectivist values in line with relevant constitutional imperatives. Introducing negligence-based liability will not only enhance the protection of personality rights but also ensure that the legal framework aligns with the transformative goals of constitutionalism, promoting a more just and equitable society. This change will help realise the constitutional promise of human dignity, equality, and freedom, reflecting the true social constitutional value of the human personality.

 

 


1. In broad terms, Klare “Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism” 1998 SAJHR 150 described the principle of adjudicative subsidiarity as follows: “... a long-term project of constitutional enactment, interpretation and enforcement committed ... to transforming a country’s political and social institutions and power relationships in a democratic, participatory and egalitarian direction.”

2. Which is known as animus iniuriandi in the context of the common law of personality. Translated from Latin, animus iniuriandi refers to “the intention to injure”. See Le Roux v Dey 2011 3 SA 274 (CC) para 129.

3. R v Umfaan 1908 TS 62 66; SAUK v O’Malley 1977 3 SA 394 (A) 402-403 and 407; De Lange v Costa 1989 2 SA 857 (A) 860-861; Minister of Justice v Homeyr 1993 3 SA 131 (A) 154; NM v Smith 2007 5 SA 250 (CC) para 55; Economic Freedom Fighters v Manuel 2021 3 SA 425 (SCA) para 36; Reddell v Mineral Sands Resources (Pty) Ltd 2023 2 SA 404 (CC) para 38.

4. See generally Parsons 1951 THRHR 192; Pauw (1976) 211-215; Burchell The Law of Defamation in South Africa (1985) 169-171; Van der Merwe and Olivier Die Onregmatige Daad in die Suid-Afrikaanse Reg (1989) 246; Knobel “Nalatige Persoonlikheidskrenking” 2002 THRHR 24; Neethling “The Right to Privacy, HIV/AIDS and Media Defendants” 2008 SALJ 43; Neethling “Onregmatigheidsbewussyn as Element van Animus Iniuriandi by Iniuria” 2010 Obiter 711-712; Knobel “Thoughts on Intention, Consciousness of Wrongfulness and Negligence in Delict” 2012 THRHR 487-490; Neethling, Potgieter, and Roos (2019) 125 fn 703.

5. Knobel 2012 THRHR 488-490.

6. As above.

7. The notion of reparations is based on the so-called “continuity thesis,” with its origin to be found in the law of torts, which contextualises the ideological function of the law of delict. In oversimplified terms, the concept of reparations encapsulates the traditional concepts of “compensation” and “satisfaction” but goes much further. Its central focus is to bring about corrective justice for rights infringements such as property, bodily integrity, and personality, pertinent to the South African law of delict. The right violation continues to exist until “there is some intervening action that remedies it,” namely reparations. However, reparations are not limited to monetary awards as the dominant position in the law of delict. They include any remedial action that remedies the wrong caused by a rights infringement, for example, an apology, among others. See generally Gardner “What is Tort Law for? Part 1. The Place of Corrective Justice” 2011 Law and Philosophy 1; Gardner “What is Tort Law for? Part 2. The Place of Distributive justice” in Oberdiek (ed) Philosophical Foundations of the Law of Torts (2014) 335; DuBois “Punishment, Reparation and the Evolution of Private Law: The Actio Iniuriarum in a Changing World” 2019 Acta Juridica 229; Zitzke “The Life Esidimeni Arbitration: Towards Transformative Constitutional Damages?” 2020 TSAR 419; Zitzke “Decolonial Comparative Law: Thoughts from South Africa” 2022 Rabel Journal of Comparative and International Private Law 190.

8. Knobel 2002 THRHR 32-33 and 36; Knobel 2012 THRHR 489-490.

9. As above.

10. Knobel 2002 THRHR 31-32; Knobel 2012 THRHR 488 and 490.

11. As above.

12. See generally Kennedy “Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication” 1976 Harvard LR 1685; Cockrell “Substance and Form in the South African Law of Contract” 1992 SALJ 40; Klare 1998 SAJHR 150; Bhana “The Role of Judicial Method in the Relinquishing of Constitutional Rights through Contract” 2008 SAJHR 300; Davis and Klare “Transformative Constitutionalism and The Common and Customary Law” 2010 SAJHR 403 412; Zitzke “Stop the Illusionary Nonsense! Teaching Transformative Delict” 2014 Acta Academia 52; Bhana “The Role of Judicial Method in Contract Law Revisited” (2015) SALJ 122; Zitzke “The History and Politics of Contemporary Common-Law Purism” 2017 Fundamina 185.

13. Post “The Social Foundations of Defamation Law: Reputation and the Constitution” 1986 California LR 711 and 716.

14. Bhana 2013 SAJHR 351 373-374; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academica 71-73; Bhana 2015 SALJ 124-133.

15. As above.

16. Bhana and Visser “The Concurrence of Breach of Contract and Delict in a Constitutional Context” 2019 SAJHR 107.

17. For such considerations, see generally Milo “South Africa’s Reasonable Publication Defence and the United Kingdom’s Public Interest Defence: Two Sides of the Same Coin?” in Koltay and Wragg (eds) Comparative Privacy and Defamation (2020) 399. Furthermore, the Constitutional Court judgment of NM v Smith serves as a potential case study to consider the application and re-evaluation of the fault standard of the actio iniuriarum.

18. Cockrell 1992 SALJ 43-44; Bhana 2008 SAJHR 302-303; Zitzke 2017 Fundamina 186-187.

19. These constitutional imperatives are unpacked in Part 4 with reference to constitutional values. AB v Minister of Social Development 2017 3 SA 570 (CC) para 56; McCrudden “Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights” 2008 The European J of Intl Law 679-680; Steinmann “The Core Meaning of Human Dignity” 2016 PELJ 1 5-8; Van Staden “Constitutional Rights and Their Limitations: A Critical Appraisal of the COVID-19 Lockdown in South Africa” 2020 AHRLJ 488.

20. Visser “Transformative Constitutionalism and the Framework of the Common Law of Personality” 2023 Stell LR 314-321.

21. As above.

22. As above.

23. As above.

24. Visser “Human Dignity and the Human Personality: Developing an Ideological Basis for the Constitutionalisation of the Common Law of Personality” 2023 SAJHR 203-206.

25. As above.

26. Visser 2023 SAJHR 207.

27. As above.

28. As above.

29. Visser 2023 SAJHR 207-208.

30. As above.

31. As above.

32. Visser 2023 Stell LR 311-312

33. Visser 2023 Stell LR 320-311.

34. Kennedy 1976 Harvard LR 1713; Cockrell 1992 SALJ 44; Klare 1998 SAJHR 152-153; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academica 56-57.

35. Kennedy 1976 Harvard LR 1713; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 56-57; Bhana 2015 SALJ 124.

36. As above.

37. Kennedy 1976 Harvard LR 1713-1715; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 56-57; Bhana 2015 SALJ 124.

38. Kennedy 1976 Harvard LR 1717; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 56-57; Bhana 2008 SAJHR 310.

39. As above.

40. Kennedy 1976 Harvard LR 1717-1718; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 56-57; Bhana 2008 SAJHR 310.

41. Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 57-60; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 109-110.

42. Klare 1998 SAJHR 149 and 159; Bhana 2008 SAJHR 302; Zitzke 2014 61; Bhana (2015) SALJ 128; Zitzke 2017 Fundamina 186; Zitzke “A Decolonial Critique of Private Law and Human Rights” 2018 SAJHR 503-509; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 109-110.

43. Zitzke 2017 Fundamina 186-187.

44. As above.

45. Visser “Revisiting the Constitutionalisation of the Common Law of Personality: Transformative Constitutionalism and Le Roux v Dey” 2020 SAJHR 247.

46. Klare 1998 SAJHR.

47. Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 107.

48. As above.

49. Bhana 2008 SAJHR 303-308; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 105-106.

50. Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 1 SA 217 (CC) para 3; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 109.

51. Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 3 SA 786 (CC) paras 62-63; Dikoko v Mokhatla 2006 6 SA 235 (CC) paras 62-80; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 109.

52. Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 109.

53. As above.

54. Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Association of South Africa: In re Ex Parte President of the Republic of South Africa 2000 2 SA 647 (CC) para 44; Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security (Centre for Applied Legal Studies Intervening) 2001 4 SA 938 (CC) para 33; Beadica 231 CC v Trustees for the time being of the Oregon Trust 2020 5 SA 247 (CC) para 71; Bhana “The Horizontal Application of the Bill of Rights: A Reconciliation of Sections 8 and 39 of the Constitution” 2013 SAJHR 353.

55. Bhana 2013 SAJHR 374-375; Bhana “The Development of a Basic Approach for the Constitutionalisation of Our Common Law of Contract” 2015 Stell LR 5.

56. Carmichele v Minister of Safety and Security para 54; Bhana 2015 Stell LR 6.

57. Klare 1998 SAJHR 159; National Coalition for Gay and Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice 1999 1 SA 6 (CC) para 28; Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs: Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs: Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 3 SA 936 (CC) para 35.

58. Bhana 2008 SAJHR 308-311; Bhana 2015 SALJ 130-133.

59. Dendy v University of the Witwatersrand 2007 8 BCLR 910 (SCA) paras 15 and 24; Gcaba v Minister for Safety and Security 2010 1 SA 238 (CC) para 56; Van der Walt Property and the Constitution (2012) 24-34 and 37; Zitzke “Constitutional Heedlessness and Over-excitement in the Common Law of Delict’s Development” 2015 CCR 286. In broad terms, in the context of the law of personality, Visser “Adjudicative Subsidiarity, the ‘Horizontality Simpliciter’ Approach and Personality Rights: Outlining an Integrated and Constitutional Reading Strategy to the Law of Personality” 2022 De Jure 128 described the principle of adjudicative subsidiarity as follows: “In terms of this approach, the starting point of this principle is to identify a potential fundamental right that is implicated between parties to a dispute in a private relationship”.

60. As above.

61. Union Government v Ocean Accident and Guarantee Corporation Ltd 1956 1 SA 577 (A) 584; Chartaprops 16 (Pty) Ltd v Silberman 2009 1 SA 265 (SCA) para 37; Van Der Walt and Midgley Principles of Delict 4th ed (2016) § 27; Loubser and Midgley (eds) The Law of Delict in South Africa 3rd ed (2017) 5 and 22-25; Neethling and Potgieter Law of Delict 8th ed (2020) 3-6.

62. Universiteit van Pretoria v Tommie Meyer Films (Edms) Bpk 1977 4 SA 376 (T) 387; Dikoko v Mokhatla para 68; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 152.

63. Fleming “The Role of Negligence in Modern Tort Law” 1967 Virgina LR 816; Cane “Mens Rea in Tort Law” 2000 Oxford J of Legal Studies 553; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) § 27; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 22.

64. Van Der Walt and Midgley (2016) §135; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 138; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 155-157.

65. Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 58.

66. Cane 2000 Oxford J of Legal Studies 535-536 and 546.

67. Dantex Investment Holdings (Pty) Ltd v Brenner 1989 1 SA 390 (A) 396. Furthermore, intent may take three forms, namely dolus directus, dolus indirectus, and dolus eventualis. For a detailed account on the explanation of the different forms of intention, see generally Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 137; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 144-147; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 159-160.

68. Khumalo v Holomisa 2002 5 SA 401 para 20.

69. Dantex Investment Holdings (Pty) Ltd v Brenner 396; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 137; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 148-149; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 160163.

70. S v Ngubane 1985 3 SA 677 (A) 686-687; Midgley “Intention Remains the Fault Criterion under the Actio Injuriarum” 2001 SALJ 435; Knobel 2002 THRHR 35.

71. Cane 2000 Oxford J of Legal Studies 545.

72. Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 26 and 148.

73. Cane 2000 Oxford J of Legal Studies 537.

74. Kruger v Coetzee 1966 2 SA 428 (A) 430; Sea Harvest Corporation (Pty) Ltd v Duncan Dock Cold Storage (Pty) Ltd 2000 1 SA 827 (SCA) para 21; Loureiro v iMvula Quality Protection (Pty) Ltd 2014 3 SA 394 (CC) paras 53-57; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 148; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 154-156; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 164-166.

75. Cape Town Municipality v Paine 1923 AD 207 216-217 and 225; Herschel v Mrupe 1954 3 SA 464 (A) 490; Weber v Santam 1983 1 381 SA (A) 410-411; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) § 148; Loubser and Midgley (2017) 154; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 169-170.

76. Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 26 and 148.

77. S v Ngubane 686-687; Cane 2000 Oxford J of Legal Studies 545.

78. Marais v Groenewald 646; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 26 and 148.

79. Knobel 2002 THRHR 36.

80. Mashinini “The Processing of Personal Information Using Remotely Piloted Aircraft Systems in South Africa” 2020 De Jure 148 and 155.

81. Knobel 2002 THRHR 31; Neethling 2008 SALJ 43; Van Der Walt and Midgley (2016) 26 and 148.

82. As above.

83. As above. Interestingly, this distinction between intent and negligence manifests in positive law through the evidentiary difficulty in establishing intent over negligence. Arguably, on a pragmatic level, intention is a difficult form of fault to prove as one is essentially tasked to determine the subjective mind of a defendant. In comparison to negligence, which hinges liability on comparing the conduct of the defendant to that of the reasonable person, it is an evidentiary challenging task to establish intention. This evidentiary difficulty makes it easier to establish negligence over intention. This then accounts for the proposition of why negligence casts the net of liability wider than intention due to this evidentiary difficulty. See Marais v Groenewald 646; Cane 2000 Oxford J of Legal Studies 542 and 553; Knobel 2002 THRHR 316; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 26.

84. As above.

85. This hypothetical draws inspiration from the Constitutional Court case NM v Smith 2007 5 SA 250 (CC). For further appraisal of this judgment, see Penfold and Milo, “Media Freedom and the Law of Privacy: NM and Others v Smith and Others (Freedom of Expression Institute Intervening as Amicus Curiae) 2007 (5) SA 250 (CC)” 2008 CCR 322-325.

86. Knobel 2002 THRHR 27; Neethling and Potgieter “Accusation of Shoplifting: Actionable Defamation or Iniuria? - Pieterse v Clicks Group Ltd 2015 5 SA 317 (GJ)” 2018 THRHR 148.

87. Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 56-57.

88. Bernstein v Bester 1996 2 SA 634 (CC) para 65; President of the Republic of South Africa v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd (Agri SA and Others, amici curiae) 2005 5 SA 3 (CC) para 36; Kennedy 1976 Harvard LR 1713; Botha “Human Dignity in Comparative Perspective” (2009) 20 Stell LR 193; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academia 56-57; Bhana 2015 SALJ 124.

89. As above.

90. Midgley 2001 SALJ 440; Van der Walt and Midgley (2016) 26.

91. As above.

92. As above.

93. Bhana 2013 SAJHR 351 373-374; Zitzke 2014 Acta Academica 71-73; Bhana 2015 SALJ 124-133.

94. Bhana 2015 SALJ 144-145; Zitzke 2018 SAJHR 500-501; Visser 2022 De Jure 126.

95. As above. In the context of the common law of personality, generally see Visser 2022 De Jure 133-137.

96. As above.

97. Neethling, Potgieter, and Roos (2019) 125-126.

98. Van der Walt Property and the Constitution (2012) 24-34; Zitzke 2015 CCR 286; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 109; Visser 2022 De Jure 128.

99. First National Bank of SA Ltd t/a Wesbank v Commissioner, South African Revenue Services 2002 4 SA 768 (CC) paras 47-48; Phumelela Gaming and Leisure Ltd v Gründlingh 2007 6 SA 350 (CC) para 35; Law Society of South Africa v Minister for Transport 2011 1 SA 400 (CC) para 83; Bhana and Visser 2019 SAJHR 111-113; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 19.

100. AK v Minister of Police 2023 2 SA 321 (CC) para 71; Zitzke “Critiquing the Komape Decision” 2019 TSAR 822; Zitzke “The Life Esidimeni arbitration: Towards Transformative Constitutional Damages?” 2020 TSAR 425; Zitzke “Transforming the Law on Psychiatric Lesions” 2021 Stell LR 259 and 263; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 19.

101. Khumalo v Holomisa para 27; Le Roux Dey 2011 3 SA 274 (CC) para 141; Knobel 2012 THRHR 488 and 490; Neethling, Potgieter, and Roos (2019) 20 and 125; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 19-20; Visser 2021 Stell LR 284.

102. S v Mamabolo (E TV, Business Day and the Freedom of Expression Institute Intervening) 2001 3 SA 409 (CC) para 41; Neethling, Potgieter, and Roos (2019) 125; Neethling and Potgieter (2020) 21-22; an Staden (2020) AHRLJ 490.

103. Knobel 2002 THRHR 31.

104. Visser 2023 SAJHR 206-208.

105. As above. Also note that in the context of the common law of personality, the constitutional value of human dignity is the central ideological axis for the constitutional interpretation of human personality. In this regard, the remaining values of equality, freedom, and ubuntu support and supplement the ideological tenets of human dignity. See Khumalo v Holomisa paras 26-28.

106. Ferreira v Levin 1996 1 SA 984 (CC) para 49.

107. Visser 2023 SAJHR 206-208.

108. As above.

109. Post 1986 California LR 711 and 716.

110. As above.

111. As above.

112. Dikoko v Mokhatla 2006 6 SA 235 (CC) para 113.

113. Lesbian and Gay Equality Project v Minister of Home Affairs 2006 1 SA 524 (CC) para 60; Albertyn and Goldblatt “Facing the Challenge of Transformation: Difficulties in the Development of an Indigenous Jurisprudence of Equality” 1998 SAJHR 254.

114. As above.

115. Ferreira v Levin 1996 1 SA 984 (CC) para 49-52.

116. As above.

117. As above.

118. S v Makwanyane 1995 3 SA 391 para 224; Mayelane v Ngwenyama 2013 4 SA 415 (CC) para 24.

119. As above.

120. As above.